Shame[1]
is looked upon as one of the most important of all emotions[2]
in everyday life and the most important of all of our social emotions. The
American sociologist Thomas J. Scheff (2003) argues that this is because shame
has more functions than other emotions. Shame is a major component for our
conscience, a moral feeling. Shame signalizes a moral transgression even
without thoughts and words. Shame comes into being in situations characterized
by a threat against inter relational bonds. It signalizes problems in a
relationship, the feeling of having failed to live up to ones social and moral
standards. Shame plays a part also in how we express, and how we comprehend all
of our other emotions. One can be so shameful over all ones emotions that they
can be totally suppressed.
Still, shame shows
itself almost invisibly because of the taboo that arises as a result of denial
and silence in our modern society[3].
My starting point for studying shame is to emphasize a social angel, how shame
shows itself in social systems. Most definitions of shame put weight on the
emotions psychological aspects. How I decide to define shame will be important
for how I carry out my study of shame. I start therefore with a discussion of
what shame is and end up with a conceptual and operational definition of shame
which integrate the self (emotional reactions) and society (social bonds). This
will make a basis for the choice of method I use for exploring shame.
Several forefathers of
sociology have made some general formulations around the importance of
emotions. Max Weber (1864-1920) wrote that values are the basis for social
structures and that all values can be understood as emotional beliefs
(1904/2006). Émile Durkheim (1858-1917) used shared emotions in creation of
solidarity through the moral society (1897/2006). Talcott Parsons (1902-1979) lifted emotions
forth as a component to our social actions and are emphasized in his classical
AGIL pattern (Adaption, Goal attainment, Integration, Latency) (1965). Karl
Marx (1818-1883) and Friedrich Engels (1820-1895) involved emotions in the
tensions between classes and in the solidarity inside the specific class that
is in a conflict or rebellion (1848/2006). All these classical formulations
have not contributed to any special new development of knowledge about
emotions, because they have only evaluated emotions on a broad basis. General
statements about emotions have in many ways very little practical use. Our
personal knowledge about emotions through experience are not general, but on
the contrary very specific. The above mentions theorists and others that have
written about emotions in general have not developed concepts about emotions,
they have not explored how emotions actually come forth in everyday life, or
collected data on emotions. Their discussions have not given us new knowledge
that will give us better insight in the emotions that we share with each other.
Gershen Kaufman (1989)
writes that shame is a taboo in our western society. We relate to studies about
shame as though they did not exist. He writes that there are several reasons
for this.
“There is a significant
shame about shame, causing it to remain hidden. The cultural
taboo surrounding human sexuality in
an early age is thus matched by an equally pronounced taboo surrounding shame
today…Lack of an adequate language with which to accurately perceive, describe,
and to bring into meaningful relationship this most elusive of human
affects…Without an accurate language of the self, shame slips quickly into the
background of awareness…Finally, psychological theorist as well as
practitioners have found it both easier and safer to explore “guilty” impulses
rather than a “shameful” self.” (p.4)
His thoughts about feeling shame about shame, our relationship to sexuality,
lack of an adequate language about shame and self, and that we are inclined to
explore guilt instead of shame just because this is an easier task, gives us
some explanations to why shame seems to be a taboo in our society today. People
feel often shame about shame and therefore risk resistance whenever one refers
to it.
This may make it
necessary to establish a new working concept about shame in order to explore it
closer. Such a concept, together with a theory and method on
emotional/relational processes and structures, might bring forth an
understanding of the close bonds between self and society. Shame is precisely
an emotion that seems to threaten these bonds.
The American sociologist Thomas Scheff calls this form for social shame
for a bonding affect (2003). Scheff is of the opinion that shame must be
defined much wider than we usually do today in order to understand the
conclusive function that shame has as a social control mechanism.
The narrowest
definitions of shame are found in our ordinary, daily language, in orthodox
psychoanalytic theory and in experimental social psychology. The wider
definitions are found in qualitative and micro linguistic research and in the
ordinary dialects of traditional societies. Among the sociologists who have
used a wide definition of shame can be mentioned George Herbert Mead
(1863-1931), Charles Horton Cooley (1864-1929) and Erving Goffman (1922-1982).
Most languages have a
word for everyday, not so serious shame and another word for the more negative
and strained form for shame. Scheff (2003) argues that the English language
lacks an adequate word for the everyday and not so serious shame. Here are some
examples:
disgrace
|
modesty
|
|
Greek
|
aischyne
|
adios
|
Latin
|
foedus
|
pudor
|
French
|
honte
|
pudor
|
Italian
|
vergogna
|
pudore
|
German
|
Schande
|
Scham
|
(Scheff and Retzinger, 1991, p.7)
One way to get by the taboo of shame
is to use a somewhat softer and less threatening member of the same family of
emotions and do like Goffman (1967/2006) who treats the embarrassment as a key
emotion to all social interaction.
A more social definition of the self
can serve as a starting point for a broader definition of shame. This because
shame comes into being in the self and strikes the whole self, at the same time
shame is social and points outwards towards society. Mead (1934/1967) suggested
that the self is a social phenomenon just as much as it is biological. His
thoughts about seeing things from the viewpoint of others just as much as from
ones own, is central to his social psychology. This way of thinking is of
central importance also for Cooley and Goffman. Mead had the need for his idea
about taking the viewpoint of the other, so that he could better explain his
concept of reflective intelligence. Mead gave little of no attention to shame
or other emotions.
Cooley (1902/2006) writes that both
shame and pride comes from seeing oneself from the viewpoint of others. His
concept of “the looking-glass self” refers directly to both shame
(mortification) and pride. He saw the principle of self-reflection in three
steps.
“ …the imagination of our appearance
to the other person; the imagination of his
judgement of that appearance, and
some sort of self-feeling, such as pride or
mortification.” (p.184).
Cooley connected the principle of inter-subjectivity to pride and shame.
Sociology and social psychology have valued and often quoted “the looking-glass
self”, but have disregarded the part that has to do with pride and shame.
Unfortunately, Cooley never came with an explanation of what he meant with
pride and shame. Both are very complex emotions. The word shame bears very many
negative associations with it, so many that it is a taboo. Cooley seems to be
inattentive to this problem.
Goffman also used the
idea that emotions were created through taking the viewpoint of the other, but
in much lesser degree than Cooley, and was more concerned with embarrassment
than shame. But more than Cooley and very much more than Mead, Goffman showed
the connection between embarrassment and taking the viewpoint of the other by
showing to a large number of examples. Goffman (1959) uses a figure called
“Everyperson” that was desperately worried about his self image in the eyes of
others. “Everyperson” always tries to present himself from his best side. Goffman
created also the important sociological point about embarrassment, which he
meant came from being offended in some way or another, either they were real or
not, expected, just a fantasy or without regards to how commonplace they might
seem to an outside observer.
Sigmund Freud
(1856-1939) and Joseph Breuer (1842-1925) gave in their book Studies on Hysteria (1895/2004) shame a central role as cause in
psychopathology, but after writing The
Interpretation of Dreams (1900/2004) Freud ignored shame in all forms of
orthodox formulations. He did this because he made anxiety and guilt into the
central emotions in psychoanalytic theory. Erik Erikson (1902-1994) rejected
Freud’s belief that guilt was the primary emotion in adults in his book on Childhood and Society (1950/1995). He
argued instead that shame was the most important, this because shame involved
the whole self and not just ones actions.
The sociologist and
social philosopher Helen Merrel Lynd (1896-1982) evolved this idea from Erikson
further in her book On Shame and the
Search for Identity (1961/1999). She used concrete examples in order to
clarify the idea of shame. She was the first to realize the need for a concept
of shame that was clearly defined and which differed from ordinary everyday
use.
Silvan Tompkins
(1911-1991), one of the most influential theorist of 20th-century
psychology and is generally considered the founder of modern affective science,
made the next step in the direction of a more social definition of shame in his
two volume writings of Affect, Imagery,
Consciousness (1963/2006). He acknowledged the central position that shame
plays in the process of becoming a self. He argued that embarrassment, shame
and guilt should be seen as members of the same family of affects. His work has
had a tremendous influence on emotion research. Researchers have since carried
out hundreds of studies on face expressions that say something about the
different emotions. But these studies have contributed little to the knowledge
of shame. This is because, firstly, shame has not been seen as a genuine
emotion, and secondly, researchers who only use snapshot pictures of face
gestures have ignored the verbal and non-verbal contexts of affects.
The psychoanalyst Helen
Block Lewis (1913-1987) developed an extensive theoretical definition of shame
and used an operational definition of shame in her work. She meant that shame
depends only on very specific aspects of social relations. This differs from
other emotions. She emphasised also the idea that shame was a social emotion,
in a bio-psycho-social way. Shame is an instinct, she says, which function is
to signalise threats to the social bonds. She suggested that shame is on the
outside of our attention. Her theory is built on hundreds of psychoanalysis therapy
sessions with patients. She used what is called as the “Gottschalk-Gleser”
method, which is a systematic method used for identifying emotions by using
transcriptions from recorded conversations. This method implies using long
lists of keywords that correlate to specific emotions, like anger, fear,
anxiety and shame. Her most important finding was that shame was found in all
of the psychotherapy sessions, that patients and therapists very seldom showed
direct signs of shame in these conversations, and that there was a relation
between shame and anger, where anger seemed to be used to hide shame. Her
research and theories on shame can be found in her book called Shame and Guilt in Neurosis (1971).
Social psychologists
like Rowland S. Miller (1997); June Price Tangney and Ronda L. Dearing (2002);
Keith Oatley, Dacher Keltner and Jennifer M. Jenkins (2006), all focus on
emotions as experimental variables. Their studies come very close to what
sociologist Thomas J. Scheff (1997) call “part/whole analysis”, inspired by the
Dutch philosopher Baruch de Spinoza (1632-1677) who argues that people are so
complicated that we can only start to understand them by looking at them part
by part (i.e. words and gestures) and put this together with the larger whole
(i.e. concepts, theories and contexts). None of the these social psychological
experimental studies look at the social dimensions of emotions.
A first step towards a
definition of shame, which makes it possible to treat the emotion in a
systematic fashion that satisfy scientific standards, is to use the concept as
a name to a class of emotions. Such emotions arise when one gets a negative
self image by looking at oneself through the eyes of others, or just by
expecting such a reaction. This will include the work of Erving Goffman
(1967/2006) with embarrassment. A social definition of shame will be in
conflict with ordinary, everyday use of the word, which is narrower, like a
form for disgrace. The research done by Helen B. Lewis (1971) has taught us
that shame, or the expectation of shame, is a continuous existence of being
found in forms most social interactions.
Shame is combined with
other emotions and creates therefore affects. Disgust and guilt would be two
good examples of this. Disgust seems to be an affect of shame and anger, where
the anger is pointed outward. Being insulted, one would maybe try to hide ones
shame and anger by being aggressive. Guilt seems to have a similar appearance,
but with the anger pointed inwards, towards one self. Guilt serves an important social function by
leading one towards doing something right in order to compensate for the wrong
one has done. But at the same time, it serves to hide ones shame, this because
it focuses on the outgoing actions, ones transgressions and the activities one
does to make right ones wrong doings. Guilt does not replace shame, but
functions instead as one of many masks that conceal shame. Shame does not go
away, it just goes underground.
If on looks at shame as
a large family of emotions, including related word and variations, the most
common emotions would be embarrassment, guilt, humiliation and similar emotions
like being sky when it is because one feels a treat to a social bond. A social
definition of shame must include both the self (emotional reactions) and
society (social bonds). If one declares that shame is created by a treat to a
social bond, regardless of how small, than a wide range of related words and
variations follow with it. Not just embarrassment, being sky and bashful, but
every kind of emotion that has to do with ones self-consciousness must be
included. Shame comes to being through a treat to a social bond and will
therefore be the most important of our social emotions. Shame is the emotion
that Émile Durkheim could have described as the social emotion, if he had
mentioned such an emotion.
Helen B. Lewis (1971)
was one of the first to treat shame in an operationally way. Her definition is
still useful and applicable for identifying shame. I have made an adapted
version of what she sees as characteristic for shame experiences. It is
important to remember that the way one positions oneself I relation to the
other is always an inferior position.
Tabel 1: Self and “Other” in shame and guilt.
Shame experiences
Self (unable)
|
“Other”
|
1. Object of scorn; contempt;
ridicule; reduced; little
|
1. The source of scorn, contempt,
ridicule
|
2. Paralyzed; helpless; passive
|
2. Laughing; ridiculing, powerful, active
|
3. Assailed by noxious body stimuli; rage,
tears, blushing
|
3. Appears intact
|
4. Childish
|
4. Adult; going away; abandoning
|
5. Focal in awareness
|
5. Also focal in awareness
|
6. Functioning poorly as an agent or
perceiver
Divided between imaging self and the “other”
Boundaries permeable; vicarious experience of
self and “other,” especially in humiliation
|
6. Appears intact
|
Guilt experience
Self (able)
|
“Other”
|
1. The source of guilt as well as of
pity and concern; regret, remorse (virtue)
|
1. Injured, needful, suffering, hurt
|
2. Intact
|
2. Injured
|
3. Adult; responsible
|
3. Dependent, by implication
|
4. Occupied with guilty acts or thoughts
|
4. Subject of thought as related to
guilt, otherwise “other” need not be involved
|
5. Functioning silently
|
5. Nothing comparable to vicarious
experiences in shame, humiliation
|
(Lewis, 1971, p.88)
Tabel 2: Working concept for shame and guilt:
Shame
|
Guilt
|
|
Stimulus
|
1. Disappointment, defeat or moral
transgression
|
1. Moral transgression
|
2. Deficiency in self
|
2. Event, act, thing for which self
responsible
|
|
3. Involuntary, self unable
|
3. Voluntary, self able
|
|
4. Encounter with “other”
|
4. Within the self
|
|
Extent of libidinal component
|
1. Specific connection to sex
|
1. Connection to aggression
|
Conscious content
|
1. Painful emotion
|
1. Affect may or may not be present
|
2. Autonomic reactions
|
2. Autonomic reactions less likely
|
|
3. Connections to past feelings
|
3. Fewer connections to past feelings
|
|
4. Many variants of shame feelings
|
Guilt feeling is monotonic
|
|
5. Fewer variations of cognitive content (the
self)
|
5. More variations of content – things in the
world
|
|
6. Identity thoughts
|
6. No identity thorughts
|
|
See Table 1
|
||
Position of the self in the field
|
1. Self passive
|
1. Self active
|
2. Self focal in awareness
|
2.Self not focal in awareness
|
|
3. Multiple functions of the self at the same
time
|
3. Self intact, functioning silently
|
|
4. Vicarious experience of “others” view of
self
|
4. Pity, concern for “other’s” suffering
|
|
Nature and discharge of hostility
|
1. Humiliated fury
|
1. Righteous indignation
|
2. Discharge blocked by guilt and/or love of
“other” discharge on self
|
2. Righteous indignation
|
|
Characteristic defences
|
1. Denial
|
1. Isolation of affect
|
2. Repression of ideas
|
2. Rationalization
|
|
3. Affirmation of the self
|
3. Reaction formation: good deeds or thoughts
|
|
4. Affect disorder: depression
|
4. Thought disorder: obsession and paranoia
|
(Lewis. 1971, p. 90-91)
Kaare T. Pettersen
References:
Cooley, Charles Horton, [1902] 2006. Human
Nature and the Social Order. New
Brunswick:
Transaction Publishers.
Davidson, Richard J., Klaus R. Scherer and H. Hill Goldsmith, 2003. Handbook
of Affective
Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Durkheim, Émile [1897] 2006. On
Suicide. London:
Penguin Books Ltd.
Erikson, Erik, [1950] 1995. Childhood
and Society. Vintage.
Freud, Sigmund, [1900] 2004. The
Interpretation of Dreams. Kessinger Publishing Co.
Freud, Sigmund and Joseph Breuer, [1895] 2004. Studies on Hysteria. Middlesex: Penguin
Books Ltd.
Goffman, Erving [1959] 1990. The
Presentation of Everyday Life. London:
Penguin Books
Goffman, Erving, [1967] 2006. Interaction
Ritual. Essays on Face-to-Face Behavior. New
Brunswick: Aldine Transaction.
Kaufman, Gershen, 1989. The Psychology of Shame. Theory and Treatment
of Shame-Based
Syndromes. New York: Springer Publishing Company.
Kaufman, Gershen, 1991. Shame. The Power of Caring. Rochester: Schenkman Books
Inc.
Kaufman, Gershen og Lev Raphael, 1996. Coming out of Shame.
Transforming Gay and
Lesbian Lives. New York: Doubleday.
Lewis, Helen Block., 1971. Shame and Guilt in Neurosis. New York:
International
Universities Press.
Lynd, Helen M., [1961] 1999. On
Shame and the Search for Identity. New
York: Science
Edtitions.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels [1848] 2006. Manifesto of the Communist Party. Cosimo
Inc.
Mead, George Herbert, [1934] 1967. Mind,
Self, & Society. Chicago:
The University of
Chicago Press.
Miller, Rowland S., 1997. Embarrasment:
Poiseand Peril in Everyday Life. New
York:
Guilford Press.
Oatley, Keith, Dacher Keltner and Jennifer M. Jenkins, 2006. Understanding Emotions.
Blackwell Publishing Ltd.
Parsons, Talcott, 1965. Theories
of Society. Simon & Schuster.
Scheff, Thomas J. and Suzanne M. Retzinger, 1991. Emotions and Violence. Shame and Rage
in Destructive Conflicts. Lexington: Lexington (Reprinted in 2001 by iUniverse).
Scheff, Thomas J., 2003. Shame in Self and Society, in Symbolic
Interaction 2: 239-262.
Tangney, June Price and Ronda L. Dearing, 2002. Shame and Guilt. New York: Guilford
Press.
Tompkins, Silvan, [1963] 2006. Affect,
Imagery, Consciousness. Volume 1 The Positive
Affects and Volume 2 The Negative Affects. New
York: Springer
Weber, Max, [1904] 2006. The
Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Academic
Internett Publishers Incorporated.
[1] The Encarta Dictionary
defines shame as a negative emotion that combines feelings of dishonour,
unworthiness, and embarrassment and offers the following synonyms: disgrace,
embarrassment, dishonour, humiliation, indignity, infamy. Pride is here
mentioned as an antonym to shame.
[2] The following are working definitions that provide a
roadmap to the terrain. There are some partial overlaps among these phenomena,
and are not offered as orthogonal constructs. For example, people in certain
moods tend to show certain emotions and feelings producing an affective style.
Emotion: refers to
a relatively brief episode of coordinated brain, autonomic, and behavioural
changes that
facilitate a response to an external and internal event of significance for
the organism.
Feelings: are the subjective representations of emotions. Note that they
can reflect any or all of
the components that constitute
emotion.
Mood: typically refers to a diffuse affective state that is often of
lower intensity than emotion,
but considerably longer in
duration. Moods are not associated with the patterned
expressive signs that
typically accompany emotion and sometimes occur without
apparent cause.
Attitudes: are relatively enduring, affectively colour beliefs,
preferences, and predispositions
toward objects or persons.
Affective styles: refers to relatively stable dispositions that bias an
individual toward a
particular emotional quality,
emotional dimensions, or mood.
Temperament: refers to particular affective styles that are apparent
early in life, and thus may
be determined by genetic
factors.
(Davidson et al, 2003. p. xiii)
[3] Many have written about this in the
last decades. I wish to mention here especially Helen Block Lewis (1971) who
explored shame over 25 years as part of her practice as a psychoanalytic
psychiatrist and the psychologist Gershen Kaufman (1989, 1991 and 1996) who has
developed a powerful and multi-dimensional
view of shame.
No comments:
Post a Comment