Kierkegaard[i]
uses the concept of shame in one way or another in a total of 176 times in his
complete works (not including his notes). In seven of his books the concept is
not used at all. It is in his book The
Works of Love (Kjerlighetens
Gjerninger, 1847, CW 12) that he uses the concept most often, 59 times. My
anticipation was that I would find shame used most often in the book he wrote
about despair, called The Sickness unto
Death (Sygdommen til Døden, 1849.
CW 15). But here he uses the concept shame only once. Why Kierkegaard focuses
on shame 59 times in a book about love and only once in a book about despair is
for me not an accidental circumstance but intentional.
This is a notion that I will comment
on further in this chapter. It is my theory that the book about despair
describes the concept of shame in great detail and that the book about love
shows a way of being freed from the suppression felt by being shamed. I will
use my interpretation of Kierkegaard as a foundation for my understanding of
the concept of shame, and show how a new light can be thrown upon leading
theory in psychology and sociology that are concerned with shame by using the
existentialistic philosophy of the Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard.
Søren Kierkegaard published the book
Sickness unto Death under the
pseudonym of Anti-Climacus. The book was written in just three months,
March-May 1848, and he waited over a year before releasing it on July 30th
1849. Some say that this book is Kierkegaards most mature piece of work, and
even call it his masterpiece (Come 1995, Grøn 1997). The first few pages of
this book are reflected in all of Kierkegaards remaining works, both those
written with pseudonym authors and those in his own name.
Kierkegaard had used the pseudonym
Johannes Climacus two times before as author for his more philosophical
entiteled books. Johannes Climaus is a man how declares himself as not being a
Christian, but instead being expectant and experimental. Johannes Climacus is the author of Philosophical
Crumbles (Philosophiske
Smuler, 1844, CW 6) and Completed Unscientific Postscript (Afsluttende
uvidenskabelig Efterskrift, 1846, CW 9 and 10). Anti-Climaus is in
many ways his opposite and declares himself for being a Christian. He is used
as the author of Sickness unto Death
and a book called Practice in
Christianity (Indøvelse i
Christendom, 1850, CW 16). The subtitle in Sickness unto Death is A
Christian Psychological Expostion for Upbuilding and Awakening. In the English
translation by Hong and Hong the term “psychological” is understood as a
philosophic anthropology or a phenomenology of human possiblities (Sickness unto Death 1980, Hong and Hong
translation, p 173).
The book consists of
two parts. I will concentrate on the first part of the book The Sickness unto Death is Despair. The
second part of the book is called Despair
is Sin. In the preface of the book, Anti-Climacus writes that all Christian
knowing ought to be concerned. Anti-Climacus is the last of the pseudonyms
invented by Kierkegaard and has a different character and function than the
rest. Anti-Climacus was invented by invented by Kierkegaard to allow him to say
what he wished to say as a Christian, keenly conscious of the gap between the
ideals he wanted to express and the actuality of his experience. Anti-Climacus
thus does not say things with which Kierkegaard would disagree, though he says
many things Kierkegaard sees as directed towards his own failings (Evans 2006).
When I refer to Kierkegaards writings, I will use the pseudonym authors that
Kierkegaard has selected. This is because Kierkegaard himself explicitly
disclaims the works of the pseudonyms:
Thus in the
pseudonymous works there is not a single word by me. I have no opinion about
them except as a third party, no
knowledge of their meaning except as a reader, not a single private relation to
them, because this would be impossible to have to a double-reflecting wessage.
(Concluding Unscientific Postskript, CW volume 10, A First and Last Declaration,
286, my translation)
.
This theme about Kierkegaard and his pseudonym authors is extremely
interesting and a great subject for further study, but it is not a part of my
investigation here and now.
Concern, he writes, constitutes the
relation to life, to the actuality of the personality. Despair on the other
hand is a sickness, not a cure as some people might think. Kierkegaard means
that we have to live with despair, and the only cure for despair is death.
In my reading of Sickness unto Death, it becomes clear to
me that Anti-Climacus is speaking of despair it coincides with what many call
shame today. The book concentrates on what happens when we are not our selves
or understood as not willing to be ourselves. I will later in this chapter put
forth new research in psychology and sociology that build on this same way of
thinking about shame, i.e. that shame is about how we perceive ourselves. I
will therefore continue my exploration by replacing despair in Sickness unto Death with shame and see
where this leads me. It could well be that Anti-Climacus used the more speak
able concept of despair because shame is so difficult and even shameful for
such an ethical man as Anti-Climacus to speak about directly. He therefore must
use an indirect form for communication, and uses the most obvious consequence
of shame, despair, when he is really taking about one of the most difficult
emotions to speak about.
The book starts by
claiming that shame is the sickness unto death. Shame is a sickness of the self
and Anti-Climacus writes that shame can therefore be threefold
- Shamed over not to be conscious of having a self (not shame in the strict sense)
- Shamed not willing to be oneself
- Shamed willing to be oneself
He then comes with a description of the concept of the self. This is not
done directly, but indirectly by taking up the theme of despair, which I chose
to understand as shame in my examination. Shame is understood as not being (or
willing to be) ones self (Grøn, 1997). If shame is to be understood as a
sickness of the self, it would seem necessary to have an understanding of what
the self is. Many have in the last decades found renewed insight in what the
self is through Anti-Climacus point of view (Pörn 1998). Anti-Climacus
understanding of the self is so precise and logical that it could be
characterized as algebraic in its precision and intensity (Come 1995).
A human being is spirit. But what is
spirit? Spirit is the self. But what is the self? The self is a relation that
relates itself to itself or is the relation’s relating itself to itself in the
relation; the self is not the relation but is the relation’s relating itself to
itself (Sickness unto Death 1962 p.
73, Hong and Hong translation 1980 p. 13).
The first word here, a human being, should be understood as the
universal way of being for all humans that shines constantly in each and every
individual even though all the differences also make each and every human
unique. Kierkegaard often used the term “The Individual” (“Hiin Enkelte”) when
addressing this universal human form for being in his books.
Anti-Climacus
formulates an equation, “A human being is spirit. But what is spirit? Spirit is
the self”. Putting together spirit and self in this way, he leaves the tendency
in earlier western thinking, by identifying the spiritual with a world as
“anti-matter” and “the hereafter”, and at the same time does something somewhat
sensational by saying that the spiritual is included in all aspects of life.
This is likely a learning that Kierkegaard received from Hegel (i.e. that the
spirit exceeds the totality of the human being). Man is according to
Anti-Climacus a synthesis of infinity and finites. The self is the synthesis
where finites is limiting and infinity is expanding. This assertion is built on
Hegelian dialectics which assumes that two elements which bring forth a
synthesis are opposites (thesis and anti-thesis) (Hegel 1977). But Kierkegaard
states that Hegel was not concerned with qualitative oppositions. Opposites are
for Hegel reconciled, mediated and always stay inside the immanence (i.e.
existing in all parts of the created world).
Then he asks “But what
is the self?” The answer he gives establishes five conditions for the mature or
realized self. These conditions are almost put forth in a prophetical fashion,
where the one awaits and foresees the next. The first two can be seen in a
humanistic frame, while the last three can be seen in a ethical/moral frame.
The five conditions or qualifications can in short be summarized like this:
- The self is a relation.
- The self is a relation which relates to itself.
- The self, as a relation which relates itself to itself, is created by another (“et Andet”) and by relating itself to itself, relates also to this another.
- The self, as a relation which does not relate itself to itself and which does not relate itself to this another, finds itself in a double disparity of shame.
- The self will find its shame completely cured when it rests transparently in the force that created it.
The double disparity of shame put forth in condition four means that
there two forms of real shame. The first one relates to ones self, and the
second relates to others. The formula for what kind of condition the self is
in, is to relate itself to itself. To be ones self builds on the force which
created it, which I understand as our ethical consciousness. A theological
explanation here could say that Anti-Climacus is talking about God as the force
that created us. I leave such theological interpretations to theologians, and
chose here a more ethical terminology.
Pure dialectically, shame is both
something positive and negative. The possibility of having this sickness is
mans advantage over other animals. To be attentive of this sickness is the
advantage moral humans have over unmoral ones. To be cured from this sickness
is the concern of ethics. It is therefore an indefinite advantage to be able to
feel shame. Shame is the disparity in the synthesis’ relationship which relates
ones self to ones self.
Someone feeling shame
does not feel shame over something. Feeling shame over something is not shame,
but a starting point, or as the doctor would say, the sickness has not yet
shown itself. The formula for all shame is to be ashamed over ones self. People
feeling shame will have a shamed way of being, they will be oneself in a shamed
way. Those feeling shame feel that they are dying, yet know that they cannot
die. This is what Anti-Climacus means by saying that shame is a sickness in the
self, a sickness unto death.
All people feel shame.
The highest demand for a person is to be a self (Løgstrup 1991). The well
informed doctor does not have an absolute belief in all the beliefs patients
give him about their health. He has a different perspective on sickness than
the patient does. Why is this? Because the doctor has a precise and wider
understanding of what it means to be healthy and he evaluates those he meets
there after. The self relates in the same way to shame. The self knows what
shame is. Shame is dialectically different from sickness, because it is a
sickness in the self. As soon as shame shows itself man was already shamed, it
becomes clear for him that he has been shamed all his life. Shame is a destiny
of the self. It relates to the indefinite and has therefore something
indefinite in its dialectics. Shame is not only dialectically different from
sickness, but in relation to shame all signs dialectical. Shame is when people
are not aware of being a self. Shame is, because it is completely dialectical,
the sickness that it is the greatest misfortune not to have. It is a gift, even
though it is the most dangerous sickness to have when one does not want to be
cured from it.
Anti-Climacus goes on
in Sickness unto Death to describe
the self as freedom. Freedom is the dialectical in positions of possibility and
necessity. The more consciousness one has - the more self. The more
consciousness - the more will. The more will - the more self. A person without
a will has no self. So according to Anti-Climacus, the more will a person has,
the more self-consciousness he also will have.
Our fantasy is an
infinity making reflection. The self is reflection and fantasy is reflection.
Fantasy is a representation of our self, which can be understood as the self’s
possibility. Our fantasy makes all reflection possible, and therefore the
intensity of our fantasy is the possibility of the self’s intensity.
While the indefinite shame is a lack
of the definite, the definite shame is a lack of the indefinite, and this is
because of the dialectical, that the self is a synthesis where the one is the
others opposite.
A self without possibilities, feels
shame and the same applies for the self without necessity. Possibilities
necessity is lacking necessity, the same way as the shame of necessity is
lacking possibilities. When a person is fainting he asks for water. When a
person feels shame, then he needs a possibility. With a possibility the person
feeling shame can begin to breathe again.
The personality is a synthesis of
possibility and necessity. The more consciousness one has, the more intense the
shame. In not being aware of ones shame, one is still not a self. But being
aware of ones self is shameful, and selflessness. The degree of self-awareness
increases the degree of shame.
The opposite of feeling shame is to
believe. The formula for belief is to relate to ones self, and to be ones self
is to have the self grounded in the moral foundation the self is built on. The
shame of weakness is to be ashamed over not wanting to be ones self.
Being ashamed over the definite, the
worldly, is pure immediateness, or immediateness with a quantitative reflection
in it. To be ashamed is to lose infinity. This form of shame is to be ashamed
over not willing to be ones self, or ashamed over wanting to be someone other
than ones self, wanting to be a new self.
Immediateness does not really have a
self, it does not know itself, and can therefore not know ones self. When the
immediateness believes to have a reflection (self-reflection) in it, the shame
is somewhat modified.
Being ashamed over the worldly, or
something worldly, is the most common form for shame. The more thoroughly the
reflection over shame becomes, the more rare this form of shame becomes.
Shame can either grow stronger to a
higher form of lead to a belief/faith. To be ashamed over the worldly is the
dialectical first impression of being ashamed over infinity or over ones self.
The self is double dialectical.
Being ashamed of and over ones self. Anti-Climacus distinguishes between the
acting self and the suffering self. This is the theme of the second part of Sickness unto Death called Despair (Shame) is Sin.
Identity
Sickness unto Death deals with not being ones self, or
understood as not wanting to be ones self. It all begins with a question about
what the self is, and the method quickly becomes quite negative. The book is
about shame (“Fortvilelse”). In shame the person is not his/herself. So what is
the connection here between question and theme? When the question about what
the self is asked, Anti-Climacus uses a negative method by speaking of shame as
not being ones self. The self here is not only determined as a relation but
also as a process. The self is a self-relation, but not only a relation to
itself, but that the relation relates to itself.
What is this self that
one relates to? Anti-Climacus translates the self to its concrete existence,
that is to the life one has lived and the concrete possibilities that this
existence gives. To become ones self means to take over ones self, what one
already is, the existence that is ones own, and that one is ones self in
relation to. The task is to grow together with ones self .
To become oneself is to become
concrete. But to become concrete is neither to become finite nor to become
infinite, for that which is to become concrete is indeed a synthesis. (Sickness unto Death, Hong and Hong
translation, 30)
And
Every human being is primitively
intended to be a self, designed to become himself. (Sickness unto Death, Hong and Hong translation, 33).
If one is to become oneself, the only way of doing so is to grow
together with what that already is.
When Anti-Climacus
speaks about the self becoming itself, the question naturally arises about what
is this self one shall become. The process part of the self (the self is about
relating oneself) explains the relational part of the self (the self being a
self-relation). The task is precisely that the individual by relating to
oneself must acknowledge oneself. The point the Anti-Climacus is making is that
the self is more than what meets the eye. Our consciousness shows that the self
relates to itself – against itself. It experiences itself as one that has one
already has related to.
A reconstruction of
what the self is, must go in two directions at the same time, both in direction
of being a relation and in being a process. Anti-Climacus radical
interpretation in the beginning of Sickness
unto Death still stands: The self is as self-relation understood as a
relation that relates to itself. But at the same time, the self-relation is concrete.
A person is in this self-relation decided by oneself, but also against oneself.
A person is oneself - and against oneself, at the same time.
If we use only the
process orientated view of the self (that the self is that the relationship
relates itself to itself), than the result is that the self is only what it is
and becomes itself through what it does. The self-relation is in a fundamental
way a self-experience. By relating to oneself lies a passiveness (that one
suffers under this relating to oneself) and a concreteness (that one is decided
through and in spite of the way one relates in). This relation between the
active and the passive, through doing and suffering, is what a theory about
subjectivity is about.
While Anti-Climacus
analysis’s shame in Sickness unto Death,
another pseudonym author, Johannes Climacus goes a different way in Concluding Unscientific Postscript (Afslutende uvitenskapelig Efterskrift
1849/1962, CW volumes 9 and 10). This book is about the problem of subjectivity
and the problem raised here is that subjectivity is to become what it is, a
subject. Instead of building subjectivity on shame, he here builds on the
problem of making a decision. The problem of becoming oneself, as a subject,
lies in making a decision and following this decision.
The problem of
subjectivity is turned the other way around in Sickness unto Death by asking what is comes from the outside and
what comes from the inside. What happens to a person and what does s/he do? In
what way is a person suffering (passive) and in what way is s/he acting
(active)? That the Sickness unto Death
is about the problem of subjectivity, is clear in that the analysis of shame as
a point of balance lies between consciousness end will. Anti-Climacus makes the
disparity of shame a question about consciousness and will.
The negative tendency in Sickness unto Death
Anti-Climacus starts the book with short sentences about what the self
is, namely a self-relation which relates itself to itself and then immediately
latter speak of shame (“fortvilelse”) a disparity for the self. The question
about the self goes directly to the subject of shame. Instead of directly
showing what it means to be oneself, Anti-Climacus goes negatively forward by
analysing the different faces of shame, i.e. the different ways in which a
person does not become oneself and therefore is not oneself.
What does this negative
tendency mean? It is a connection between becoming oneself and not being
oneself. The normative part (becoming oneself) goes through the negative part
(shame, not being oneself) in the double meaning that the normative part ( to
become oneself in order to be oneself) partly assumes and partly is an answer
to the negative possibility (not being oneself). The task of becoming oneself
supposes that a person can indeed loose oneself. A human being first becomes
oneself by freeing oneself of shame. This negative method is not a superfluous
detour, but the normative goal. To become oneself is to win (back) oneself, but
in order to win oneself it is necessary first to loose oneself.
[i] The Danish philosopher Søren
Kierkegaard (1813-1855) died only 43 years of age but managed to write in his
lifetime a total of 28 books, thousands of pages of notes and in his last few
years of his life he fought a battle with the Danish church by writing a
newspaper in 10 publications called the Moment (“Øyeblikket”). His complete
works were first published in 1901-06, and revised in 1920-36 in a 15 volume
edition. The revised version was published again in 1962-63 in 19 volumes. It
is this edition I have used in my reading and interpretation of Kierkegaard. A
new edition of his complete works are now being published in Danmark together
with research volumes to all his writings. An enormous publication, the largest
in Danmarks history, with over 50 volumes. But since this publication is still
ongoing and not completed, I will use the last available edition called Søren Kierkegaard, Samlede Værker
(Complete Works, hereafter noted as CW) in 19 volumes published in 1962-63. I
will note specifically when I use books printed in English translations and
when I use my own translations from the Danish edition.
No comments:
Post a Comment